Thursday, September 21, 2023
spot_img
HomeGeopolitical CompassEast AsiaIn Praise of Lesser Evils: Can Realism Repair Foreign Policy?

In Praise of Lesser Evils: Can Realism Repair Foreign Policy?

Author: Emma Ashford

Affiliation: Georgetown University and the Reimagining US Grand Strategy Program at
Stimson Center
Organization/Publisher: Foreign Affairs
Date/Place: September-October 2022/ USA
Type of Literature: Book Review
Word Count: 3622

Link: https://www.foreignaffairs.com/reviews/praise-lesser-evils-realism-foreign-policy-
emma-ashford

Keywords: Classical Realism, Structural Realism, Geopolitics, Hyper-rationalism, Morals,
Human Factors, War in Ukraine, the US Foreign Policy
Brief:
In this article, Ashford critically reviews two recent books about Realism in International
Relations: “The Atlantic Realists: Empire and International Political Thought between
Germany and the United States” by Matthew Specter, and “Unwritten Future: Realism and
Uncertainty in World Politics” by Jonathan Kirshner. Both books address the limitations and
potential of realism, focusing on “Classical Realism”, which is based on a negative view of
human nature. Specter’s book examines the origins of classical realism in the pre-World War I period, attempting to uncover what he considers “the malevolent historical roots” of realist philosophy and its terminology. Kirshner’s book, on the other hand, aims to rehabilitate classical realism as a framework for understanding modern geopolitics, and to confront “Structural Realism” (Neorealism), which the author sees as having analytical shortcomings, hyper rationality, and a lack of moral consideration. Structural realism (both defensive and offensive) has come to dominate over other strands of realism and has become synonymous with realism in general.
The two books come amid growing questions about the feasibility and relevance of
realism in explaining current wars and great power competitions, particularly the Ukrainian
war. A number of prominent realists, led by John Mearsheimer, have argued that this war
was a result of the structural factor of NATO’s eastward expansion, rather than the
aggressive actions of President Putin, which has led to a decline in realism’s popularity.
Opponents of realism have also criticized the theory as “meaningless”, as the war in
Ukraine seems to demonstrate. This has led to a revival of the historical debate about the
ethical dimension of realism, with some arguing that a realistic analysis of the harsh
realities of international relations (based on anarchy and states’ pursuit of security and
survival, acting in accordance with national interest rather than moral principles) endorses
selfish behavior by states rather than providing a positivist diagnosis. So the realists have
been accused of having no morals at all, as the debate on the Ukraine war demonstrate.
For such reason Robert Gilpin wrote -in 1996- his famous essay, “No One Loves a Political
Realist.” The article is divided into four parts. In the first part, the author sets the context of the growing criticism of realism, which has led to a decline in its popularity after it
gained acceptance among elites and the general public due to its often reasonable
analysis of the ideological American foreign policy driven by liberal internationalism
over the past three decades. Ashford believes that while realism provides useful broad
lines of analysis regarding the war in Ukraine (such as the argument that NATO
expansion into post-Soviet space contributed significantly to the outbreak of the war), it is
flawed in many details. She also argues that the war in Ukraine demonstrates that some
realist theories are as simplistic and unhelpful in explaining the conflict as they were
during times of global geopolitical upheaval. According to Ashford, the realist theories
presented in Specter and Kirshner’s books may not offer new insights, but they do review
and update our understanding of the pragmatic and analytical model of classical
realism, which may be the most suitable model for our multipolar world.
In the second part of the article, Ashford discusses Specter’s critique of classical
realism and realism in general. Specter offers an alternative narrative on the origins of
realism, examining the intellectual foundations of realism and the biographies of
prominent (German and American) founding figures of realism such as Hans
Morgenthau, Wilhelm Grewe, and Carl Schmidt. Specter argues that the common
narrative of realism, which is promoted by the realist Edward Hallett Carr, is false and
that classical realism has dark imperial origins. This narrative claims that classical realism
was the intellectual reaction of German-American thinkers such as Morgenthau to the
bloody wars of the 20th century. These thinkers rejected the idealism of US President
Woodrow Wilson, whose failure to establish a League of Nations that would resolve
conflicts between nations through law and norms after World War I led to the rise of
Nazism and the outbreak of World War II. In response, these thinkers returned to classic
notions of Realpolitik as represented in the works of Thucydides and Machiavelli and
embodied by the German leader Otto von Bismarck. Specter disputes this narrative,
arguing that the classical realists invented a noble line of great thinkers, such as
Thucydides and Hobbes, because their ideas fit the classical realist worldview while
avoiding their more questionable historical antecedents from the 19th century imperial
geopoliticians. Additionally, Specter refutes the association of realists with “Bismarckian
Realpolitik” and tries to prove the connection of realism with an anti-realpolitik imperial
German school, “the Weltpolitik,” which is guided by social Darwinism and grants great
powers the right to geopolitical expansion and domination. These ideas were embodied in Wilhelm II’s policy in the late 19th century,
as well as in Hitler’s policy during World War II.
Ashford praises Specter’s genealogical work, but disagrees with some of his findings. She
argues that there is nothing wrong with contemporary scholars seeking intellectual clues
from history to support their case, and that Specter does not show how contemporary
realists’ borrowing from historical concepts undermines the validity of their arguments.
While it is true that classical realism formulated its arguments using terms familiar to 20th
century imperialists, it also added terms such as “ethical seriousness” and “caution” to its
legacy. If there are darker variants of realism in history, this should not invalidate more
modern incarnations of the theory, such as “defensive realism”, which is a more moral
approach that does not accept immoral principles or the early imperial roots of realism.
In the third part of the article, Ashford discusses Kirshner’s “Unwritten Future”. Unlike
Specter, Kirshner finds much value in classical realism for the analysis of today’s world and
calls on contemporary scholars to revive it due to its analytical richness based on the
crucial role of intellectual and internal political factors. He focuses on recent
academic works that highlight the role of factors such as honor, pride, and prestige in
international affairs, which are core factors for classical realists. He also criticizes structural
realism, arguing that it falls into a “hyper-rationalist” view of the world that ignores the
moral factor. Neorealism overestimates the rational causes of war and cannot explain
anything beyond the stasis of the international system. Kirshner poses a series of
problems that structural realists have struggled with recently, such as how to reconcile
morality with a fundamentally amoral theory, and the malleability of the concept of
the national interest. He also argues that structural realism is better at pointing out the
errors of other approaches than at suggesting its own solutions, and cannot fully explain
why and when wars happen or how leaders and populations will react when they do.
This is why he emphasizes the importance of integrating human factors, which
classical realism focuses on, in the analysis of wars.
Ashford attributes Kirshner’s perception of the “hyper-rational” language of structural realists to their attempt to make their beliefs about international politics “scientific,” rather
than appearing as ideological as they do to their liberal opponents. Liberalists
believe that states can rise above power politics and transcend conflict through trade,
international institutions, and international law, while realists disagree and see a lot of
ideology and political delusions in liberalist arguments. This is why the language of realists
is often seen as more rational, less ideological, and lacking in moral consideration.
However, Kirshner argues that both realism and liberalism have ideological
underpinnings, and that realists should stop pretending to be scientists and return to the
messier terrain of classical realism, which is more analytically rich.
In the last part of the article, Ashford defends the virtues of realism, emphasizing the
need for it to explain international affairs or guide American foreign policy despite its
limitations. In response to critics who argue that realism succeeds more in criticism
than in offering alternatives, Ashford points out that there is no single political realism.
There are different views within the realist paradigm and among realists on various
international issues, such as how to deal with China. This has made it difficult for realists to
shape policies within the current US administration or its successor. However, realists
still put pressure on US administrations to justify their policy choices or adopt
more pragmatic and non-ideological policies, despite their complex history with US
policymakers.
Although both books provide a critical overview of the problems facing realism, they fail to
offer alternatives. Ashford believes Kirshner’s book is relatively better in this regard, as it
assesses what it would mean in practice to rehabilitate classical realism. For example, it
explores the shortcomings of classical realism and incorporates issues of political
economy into its framework, as well as incorporating classical realist views into current
policy debates to guide them. However, Ashford also criticizes some inconsistencies in
Kirshner’s vision. While arguing that great powers have an opportunity to reassess their
global commitments, he also calls on the United States to maintain the status quo,
claiming that major changes are incompatible with realism’s emphasis on prudence. In
contrast, Ashford believes that Specter largely punts on the question of the future of US
foreign policy. He makes it clear that realism is not a reasonable path forward, at least not
until it incorporates postcolonial, feminist, and critical theoretical insights, because it is too
respectful of imperialist approaches, too undemocratic, and too rooted in ethically
questionable philosophy. This distaste, according to Ashford, reflects the progressives’
concern about pragmatism and moderation in foreign policy when these concepts come
into conflict with universal values. Realists are well aware of these problematic issues. In
foreign policy, realism is often a choice between the lesser of evils. Realism does not
condone “political ideals and moral principles, but it requires indeed a sharp distinction
between the desirable and the possible,” as Morgenthau wrote. Pretending that moral
principles or values can override all constraints of power and interest is not political realism; it is political fantasy. Finally, Ashford believes that with the world’s shift towards multipolarity, realism will once again become more important for the conduct of US foreign policy.
By: Djallel Khechib, CIGA Senior Research Associate

RELATED ARTICLES

LEAVE A REPLY

Please enter your comment!
Please enter your name here

- Advertisment -
Google search engine

Most Popular